logo

43 pages 1 hour read

Edmund Burke

Reflections On The Revolution In France

Nonfiction | Essay / Speech | Adult | Published in 1790

A modern alternative to SparkNotes and CliffsNotes, SuperSummary offers high-quality Study Guides with detailed chapter summaries and analysis of major themes, characters, and more.

Section 3Chapter Summaries & Analyses

Section 3 Summary

In the next section, Burke describes how the National Assembly slowly disbands or destroys each of its institutions. To equalize their country, the Assembly razes its political landscape. Their first step is to disband the monarchy. However, the monarchy, Burke believes, is a standing institution that offers dignity and inspires loyalty in France. He believes the monarchy embodies a chivalry that gives European natures character, but argues that those left out of that power (those in power now in the Assembly) might have long desired the bitter fall of such an institution. Burke laments, “I knew, indeed, that the sufferings of monarchs make a delicious repast to some sort of palates” (72). He uses this as an example of the Assembly pursuing a selfish desire over what is best for their country.

Without a central figure or a moralizing figure like a king or other institution, like a church, Burke predicts that morals of a more serious nature will fall out of fashion as well. Once civility is gone, law and order are not far behind. Under institutions, men behave well because society is based on reciprocal rights and social responsibilities. Under an absence of such direction, men will behave out of private interest. Burke warns again of a society where men act out for their own gain:

[o]n the scheme of this barbarous philosophy, which is the offspring of cold hearts and muddy understandings, and which is as void of solid wisdom, as it is destitute of all task and elegance, laws are to be supported only by their own terrors, and by the concern, which each individual may find in them, from his own private speculations, or can spare to them from his own private interests (77).

Here, Burke suggests that man attained his better self when he fell under the rule of a guiding institution; under this system, he sinks to the lowest ranks of social responsibility.

Burke instead feels that man is better for sharing in part of a greater social structure. Burke notes, in England “[w]e are afraid to put men to live and trade each on his own private stock of reason, because we suspect this stock in each man is small, and that individuals would be better to avail themselves of the general bank and capital of national, and of ages” (87). Here, he is not afraid to express himself in opposition to the popular theories of the Enlightenment because he takes refuge in the most lasting power: the long duration of time-proven establishments in England.

Another establishment Burke finds under attack is religion. Burke criticizes the Enlightenment’s propaganda in regard to pro-atheism and the denigration of the church. Again, belittling the thinkers of the Enlightenment, he states, “If our religious tenets should even want a further elucidation, we shall not call on atheism to explain them. We shall not light up our temple from that unhallowed fire” (90). He goes on to address how institutions like the church are not fads, and, if ever England came into conflict with such an institution of import, “We found these old institutions, on the whole, favorable to morality and discipline; and we thought they were susceptible to amendment, without altering the ground” (100). Burke believes the church provides the moral backbone of English society.

Burke also discusses the influence that writers of the Enlightenment had on the diminishment of institutions. When banding together, “Writers, especially when they act in a body, and with one direction, have great influence on the publick mind; the alliance therefore of these writers with the monied interest had no small effect of removing the popular odium and envy which attended that species of wealth” (112).  

Section 3 Analysis

Burke posits that France is designed in the shape of the monarchy, and has a court, servants, land, power, and an image. In the absence of a monarchal figurehead:

All the pleasing illusions, which made power gentle, and obedience liberal, which harmonized the different shades of life, and which, by a bland assimilation, incorporated into politics the sentiments which beautify and soften private society, are to be dissolved by this new conquering empire of light and reason. All the decent drapery of life is to be rudely torn off (77).

Although Burke alludes to the Assembly as an “empire of light and reason” (77), he does so sarcastically; the light they allow in is too harsh, revealing the indignities like so many specks of dust in the morning sunlight. According to Burke, this does a great disservice to many of the binding contracts of civil society including manners, politeness, and chivalry—those many pleasing qualities that define the old European guard.

As to the abolishment of their monarchy, Burke considers the idea of a constitutional monarchy more prudent than rationalism: “Have these gentlemen never heard, in the whole circle of the worlds of theory and practice, of anything between the despotism of the monarch and the despotism of the multitude” (124). This speaks to the radical nature of the men of the Assembly; to them, it is between two desperate choices: an absolute monarch or a direct democracy. Burke states that once the seed of radicalism is planted in the brain, the thought process fails to consider any option but the extreme. As a result, in their effort to adopt an extreme government that often does not work in practice, Burke predicts France’s ruin (125), thus reverting back to some ruling power taking control.

blurred text
blurred text
blurred text
blurred text