35 pages • 1 hour read
Sigmund FreudA modern alternative to SparkNotes and CliffsNotes, SuperSummary offers high-quality Study Guides with detailed chapter summaries and analysis of major themes, characters, and more.
Summary
Chapter Summaries & Analyses
Key Figures
Themes
Index of Terms
Important Quotes
Essay Topics
Tools
Freud opens by noting that while eliminating religion may lead to an overall improvement in society, he believes that everyone is terrified that something terrible could happen if religion were to be lost, “as though it would expose civilization to a still greater danger” (40). In this chapter, Freud will argue that instead of causing a descent into chaos, getting rid of religion will only strengthen peoples’ ties to society, in particular by changing their relationship to laws.
Freud takes as an example laws against murdering. Freud explains how the prohibition of killing naturally comes about in society as being killed represents “an equal danger for everyone” (40), so people join together in a community to collectively prohibit murder. However, civilization instead explains the prohibition of murder through religion, turning the law into a sacred proclamation issued by God. Freud believes that using religion to justify the law provides it with “a character of sanctity and inviolability” that spreads to all laws (41), making the law seem to be both universal and something that can never be altered. If the masses instead understood law as something socially constructed by humans, they might view it more favorably and seek its improvement.
The rest of the chapter is focused on comparing religion with the psychoanalytic concept of neurosis. Psychoanalysts like Freud believe that as each individual grows from a child to an adult, they learn to repress certain instinctual urges that society has deemed immoral. Some individual struggle to repress their urges, developing a neurosis as a result—such as anxiety or depression. Such neuroses often involve obsessive behavior as the individual attempts to repress their desires. Freud believes that religion, with its role in repressing urges such as that of murder, could be seen as “the universal obsessional neurosis of humanity” (43). Freud argues that if individuals must overcome their personal neuroses to become healthy, functioning adults, then religion must also be overcome by “replacing the effects of repression [with] the results of the rational operation of the intellect” (44).
The chapter opens with a series of objections from Freud’s imaginary opponent, who points out what appear to be a number of contradictions in Freud’s thinking. The opponent believes that Freud’s argument is based on the idea “that the believer can be turned into an unbeliever” (46), while Freud also asserts that believers are unable to be swayed by rational arguments against religion. The opponent also claims that Freud presents two opposing views of human nature. At the same time that Freud presents humans as ruled by animalistic urges, he also argues that humans are capable of embracing a rationalistic view of the universe. The opponent finally brings up “the French Revolution and Robespierre” as an example of a time when humans attempted to relinquish religion that resulted in chaos (46).
Freud counters that he is not attempting to reach devout religious believers, who he agrees are “bound to the teachings of religion by certain ties of affection” and not likely to turn away from religion (47). However, Freud believes there is a large number of religious followers who only follow because they feel “intimidated by the threats of religion” and are likely to give up on religion as scientific thinking spreads through society (47). Freud believes that it is crucial to provide these people with other reasons for supporting society and civilization aside from religious ones, as they will otherwise turn hostile towards society.
Freud then provides an explanation for his views on human nature. Freud believes that humans currently struggle to repress their urges and require the institution of religion to help keep them from following through on their instinctual desires. However, Freud does not believe that humanity inherently behaves this way; rather, he thinks humanity could learn to embrace rational thinking through a proper education. Freud argues that “religious education” prevents individuals from developing their intellectual capabilities to their fullest potential. By forcing religious ideas onto children at an early age, we take away their ability to critically interrogate religion. Freud imagines that one could replace religious education with an “education to reality” (49), which will help individuals acknowledge and deal with their utter “helplessness” and “insignificance” in the universe.
The chapter opens with a last set of objections from Freud’s opponent, who now takes issue with what he perceives as naïve idealism in Freud’s argument. The opponent sums up Freud’s argument with sarcasm: “That sounds splendid! A race of men who have renounced all illusions and have thus become capable of making their existence on this earth tolerable!” (51).
The opponent believes that such a societal transition is unlikely to happen. Further, he argues that it would only be possible if one were to replace religion “by means of another system of doctrines” (51)—such as scientific thinking—which would only reproduce the problems with religious institutions. The opponent believes it is impossible to educate individuals in society without relying on some form of indoctrination that imposes moral values from a very young age. As religion has a centuries-old history and is proven to help people with living their lives, the opponent believes religion should be kept as an institution.
Freud responds by explaining that he agrees with his opponent about “how difficult it is to avoid illusions” and concedes that he may be attempting to replace one form of illusion with another (53). However, Freud contends that the difference is that scientific thinking can acknowledge its errors and is constantly seeking to improve the arguments in support of it. In contrast, religious thinking insists that it is completely free of errors and punishes anyone who dares to question it.
Freud ends by arguing that it is only inevitable for scientific thinking to overtake religious ideas: “The voice of the intellect is a soft one, but it does not rest till it has gained a hearing” (53). Freud contends that while both science and religion promise a “state of bliss,” religion promises this is immediately achievable in the afterlife, while scientific thinking promises to achieve such a state on Earth, albeit years in the future “for a new generation of men” (54). Freud finally argues that science cannot be considered an illusion, as its methods allow one to obtain testable knowledge about the nature of “the reality of the world” (55).
In the final section of the book, Freud switches from analyzing religion’s development to speculating on what role religion may have for the future of society. Freud believes that religion must be seen as analogous to an individual psychological neurosis on the level of society. In psychoanalysis, a neurosis is understood as an obsessive behavior that arises in children as they struggle to repress their instinctual urges. While most individuals naturally overcome these neuroses as they grow into adults, some individuals continue to struggle into adulthood and require “psychoanalytic treatment” to get rid of their neuroses. Freud argues that religion should be considered the “universal obsessional neurosis of humanity” (43). While religion may have played a part in repressing humanity’s instincts, Freud now believes that society’s development requires it to fully leave behind religion.
However, Freud does not believe that one can simply eliminate religion without transforming human society so that religion’s functions are fulfilled elsewhere. Freud argues that civilization’s educational system must be altered so that individuals gain the ability to repress their instinctual urges without the external force of religion. While Freud is vague on what exactly such an education will look like, he describes it as an “education to reality” that refuses to use illusions to make individuals ignore “their helplessness and their insignificance in the machinery of the universe” (49). Rather than teach children to believe in a God who protects them, Freud believes that children should be brought up to embrace rational and scientific thinking.
In the final chapter, Freud’s opponent contends that he is merely suggesting that society replace one form of indoctrination with “another system of doctrines” (51). The opponent argues that it is impossible to educate children without forcing them to accept some system of belief, whether that system is religion or science. While Freud acknowledges “how difficult it is to avoid illusions” (53), he argues that there are several traits that distinguish science from religion. Religion often depends on a “prohibition of thought” (51), forbidding its followers from questioning its teachings or expressing doubt. In contrast, science encourages such investigations into its teachings and seeks to correct itself if someone discovers a scientific conclusion to be mistaken. Freud believes that attempts to preserve religion are futile, as humankind will naturally embrace rational thinking as it continues to develop: “in the long run nothing can withstand reason and experience, and the contradiction which religion offers to both is all too palpable” (54).
By Sigmund Freud